The single greatest error of the Enlightenment was the concept of universal human rights. Of course it wasn’t entirely a concept that popped into existence during the Enlightenment, but the idea that all law could be be created from scratch, ignore all prior tradition or moral guidance, and theorise into existence a perfect political settlement, probably was. Even Aristotle’s philosopher-king was not so boldly hubristic as the notion of universal human rights enforced across vastly different nations by some as yet undefined Authority backed primarily by abstract Proper Nouns.
Are there really things which every man, woman and child is entitled to, or people we would trust to deliver them?
No.
There are no universal human rights. All rights are conditional and contextual. All rights are differentiated.
Should I suppose that a citizen and a non citizen have the exact same rights? In that case I destroy the reality and purpose of citizenship.
Should I suppose that a child raping foreigner has the exact same rights as a citizen who is a loving, decent, protective parent? In that case I reward child rape equally with good parenting, which is a moral obscenity.
Should a nation concern itself more with the rights of people with whom it is at war, than it does with the protection and defense of its own civilians? In which case one asks the people it rules to take on all the risks and sacrifices of war, while offered none of the advantages and protections of a different status to the enemy.
Are the rights of a child identical to the rights of an adult? If they are, then society may make no sane and sensible recognition of the basic facts of human experience, either by recognising the vulnerability and immaturity of children, or by recognising the wisdom and experience of age.
The moral foundations of proper action do not rest in universal human rights. They rest in natural justice. Natural justice is fitting your thoughts and actions to what is most natural-a framing which instantly tells us that of course the rights of a child and an adult are different, of course the rights of a human being and an animal are different, of course the rights of a citizen and a foreigner are different, and of course justice discriminates and selects according to context and objective reality rather than according to the universal application of the same abstraction in every instance.
For example I do not have a universal right to violence. But if I am being physically attacked, my right of response changes, because it is natural and just to defend oneself. The context matters and alters the rights I possess.
As does the difference between me pursuing a thing freely, and being granted it by others. There isn’t a universal human right to a family life. Natural justice is sufficient to tell us that if someone slaughters an innocent family, that is a wicked thing. But asking others to feed and house my family and preserve our connection despite me doing criminal and stupid things that break it (like entering another country illegally)? No, that is not a natural right at all. The Declaration of Independence, which is a very Enlightenment document in its framing of grand rhetoric….nevertheless has the profound wisdom to point out that it is the pursuit of happiness which is a right, and not the possession of it.
But in practical terms even life and liberty are not absolute universal rights. Or else we would have no laws and prisons at all. Life and liberty are rights which a government is legitimately equipped only to defend as much as it may for its own citizens, an even there may be morally required to limit for the protection of others.
It’s quite clear today that our entire social ethics and legal systems have however become corrupted by the misapplication of universal rights. The practical instances of human rights lawyers and systems becoming perverse impediments to real justice are manifold. It is the universal human rights industry that forces western nations to fund their own erasure. It is the underlying belief that there are no distinctions between the basic rights human beings possess that ends of prioritising foreigners above citizens and criminals above the law abiding. Human rights lawyers become the most highly remunerated defenders and supporters of the most vile people on the planet. In the name of universal human rights, terrorists can kill innocent people, and then while evading justice for their crimes in some Third World desert or mountain range ring lawyers in London to start insisting on their alleged rights, with this assistance in the end being paid for taxpayers who might well have been the targets of their terrorist bombings.
More widely, virtually every extreme perversion, depravity or anti social lunacy and fetish advances itself on the basis of alleged universal human rights. It is an insult to these universal rights if an Army doesn’t want to arm and train people on who are on mind and body altering drugs. It is a contravention of human rights to protect your citizens from foreign crime cartels. And it’s a terrible human rights tragedy if somebody doesn’t conform to demanded imaginary pronouns. Apparently there is now a universal human right for a man to dress as a woman before sexually grooming childen.
What might be called universal human rights extremism dominates the legal system and modern ethics. Similarly, race based modern denials of basic rights to white majorities are predicated on the idea that obviously anti-white legal disparities are actually ‘social justice’, that is, a means of protecting the universalism of human rights within society as a whole.
In contrast to these things I’m going to use the term natural justice, but I should explain that a little. Natural justice has a different historic meaning and a specific legal meaning too. Historically, Classical Roman and Greek philosophers and lawyers meant something slightly different by natural law than was meant by medieval writers who discussed the same thing, and Thomas Aquinas may have commented on Aristotle’s idea of natural justice in a far more extensive way than Aristotle himself opined on it. Aristotle though seems to have contrasted laws which are particular to a specific region or culture, reflecting its nature, to laws which might be said to be more widely found, appealing to what seems natural to all men in all places:
“Universal law is the law of Nature. For there really is, as every one to some extent divines, a natural justice and injustice that is binding on all men, even on those who have no association or covenant with each other. It is this that Sophocles' Antigone clearly means when she says that the burial of Polyneices was a just act in spite of the prohibition: she means that it was just by nature:
"Not of to-day or yesterday it is, But lives eternal: none can date its birth."
And so Empedocles, when he bids us kill no living creature, he is saying that to do this is not just for some people, while unjust for others:
"Nay, but, an all-embracing law, through the realms of the sky Unbroken it stretcheth, and over the earth's immensity."[24]”
In other words we might distinguish written down local, regional and cultural laws from ‘laws of nature’ which are not necessarily written down but which appeal to the heart as natural and just. Laws against robbery may differ, but every man feels the injustice of being robbed. Codes of marriage and property vary, but every culture works out some kind of system for these and men and women may be aggrieved or pleased by similar things across different cultures.
In English and English derived law, natural justice is more specifically about legal practices designed to combat bias and unfairness. The concept of fairness was a very, very dominant one in English law and culture and in Anglo descended understanding of what justice is. So ‘natural law’ in English derived legal codes means rules for instance against judges and juries being biased, rules designed to ensure equal treatment of different persons (equality under the law) and rules regarding the ethics of those enacting the law.
In a strange way what we have then in something like a contest between ‘social justice’ and ‘natural justice’ is two competing and exactly opposite visions of how you obtain fairness and equality (early English jurists even spoke about equity, but in an entirely different way to modern radical progressives). In the traditional version of fairness, the law applies universally in the way it is conducted, following the same fair practices to limit bias. Within that, it can still recognise contextual and status differences, like the difference between a citizen and a non citizen and them having different rights. What’s universal is not the outcome, but the application of the process. The same kind of crime is dealt with in the same way without personal bias intruding. That’s justice. But in modern social justice, it’s alleged that some imported and alien groups are automatically unfairly treated, so the job of the law is to shift its treatment depending on who appears before it. For those who believe in older conceptions of anti bias and anti personal prejudice means of enforcing fairness, this ‘adjusted justice’ is inherently unfair and unjust (and they are right, it is).
Under modern social justice and universal human rights bias, then, the law becomes just by extending the same or even superior rights globally, to people who aren’t citizens and in ways that prioritise groups that in a pre-determined manner (derived from grievance hierarchy charts) are considered automatically oppressed.
There are some ways then in which the consideration for fairness and the idea of equality under the law applies to both modern injustices and traditional protections of justice, and just as the prioritisation of non white minorities can begin with classical liberal movements addressing genuine injustice, so too can the equality under the law aspects of a natural law approach be used to justify treating non citizens as if they were citizens or treating proven violent criminals as if they were law abiding persons with special rights that matter more than actual justice. What we see of course in both instances is the corruption of an idea into its eventual opposite, a process particular.y evident in how we have gone from granting blacks or gays equal treatment to giving reduced sentences based on skin colour or to pretending that public indecency is fine from certain groups.
For the purposes of this article though my definition of natural justice does not require knowledge of the history of English jurisprudence or of what Cicero, Aristotle, and Aquinas said about natural justice either. For me, natural justice means what would clearly and obviously strike the average person (the Man on the Clapham Omnibus, unencumbered by extreme modern distortions) as fair and just because it accords with very obvious and very sensible truths that are recognised in the things which disgust and revolt us as well as the things which defend and protect us. Natural justice does not say that the whole world is subject to the same abstract rights. It says that it is perfectly normal, natural and sane to in our portion of the world frame rights in accordance with our safety, security, culture and identity without any shame in prioritising our own citizens and culture.
And when we think of things that are morally universal and should be treated in the same way regardless of who does them, we are not thinking that an asylum seeker has the exact same rights to remain in our country as a citizen has, but that each and every child in our country has the right to expect that the law will punish people who rape them and seek by every possible means to ensure that they aren’t raped.
People who believe in universal human rights will say that they only assert things which are themselves naturally just, such as a right not to be tortured in vile ways. But this moral argument for universal human rights is in fact a false one. Ultimately, it is not the innate rights of another that tells us not to torture innocent people. It is a moral stricture we apply to ourselves, so that we might be better than rabid animals. Disgust at the transformation done to ourselves, shame at bestiality and barbarism in ourselves, and guilt in response to loss of self control and self restraint, are in reality more certain restraints on behaviour than any external, abstract and universal declaration of the rights of another. It is not the purpose of the law to offer kindness to terrorists, rapists and murderers. It is the purpose of the law to prevent these actions and punish these people. The law can’t teach people decent morality after the crime by being nice to them. The decent moral expectations exist first, provided by tradition and culture, and the law then enforces them for the protection of every innocent citizen. And the decent moral expectation requires harsh treatment of vile actions.
If a terrorist were equipped with shame and guilt regarding the murder of innocents, he would police himself more effectively than any State apparatus of surveillance and law can manage to do. What the abstract declaration of a universal right distorts and replaces is the necessity of moral teaching which allows a natural human capacity for shame and guilt to be nurtured in sane and responsible ways. When human beings behave in vile and unnatural ways, it is in some instances due to some physiological disorder or incapacity, but far more often it is due to depraved example and cultural and religious instruction which applies shame and guilt to the wrong things. Just as with individuals, moral systems themselves do not have universal rights, and should not be treated as exactly the same regardless of the morals they instill. Some are good and beneficial and some are evil and harmful. Therefore some have rights which others do not. Pretending otherwise is a natural injustice.
If I say that human rights are universal, really I am saying that a bestial, savage terrorist has a humanity that is somehow the same as the humanity of his victims, and that his rights are the same and as important as the rights of those he murders. But this is not true. By his actions being less human than theirs, so too are his rights lower than theirs, and natural justice knows that to fail to distinguish between him and them is to do an injustice.
Status can justly moderate rights, as with the citizen and the non citizen, or as with the child and the adult. Behaviour, too, can and should moderate rights, as with the innocent and the guilty, the responsible and the feckless, the law abiding and the criminal. In this context then what does an abstract declaration of universal rights do, except extend the protection some by natural justice deserve, to those who by natural justice are not deserving of it? Even when we distinguish those being deserving of extra protection within society, considering action against them particularly heinous, there is a natural justice to follow which guides us better than universal declarations do. It is natural and just to be more protective of children and the elderly, in recognition of their real and unavoidable vulnerability. Yet today we say ‘vulnerable groups’ and by that designate skin colour, or foreigners, or migrants and asylum seekers, or exotic religion, and pretend that these innately deserve extra protection, when they do not.
What we have seen with universal human rights, is that they become the means by which natural justice is denied. Beginning from the idea that everyone,no matter their status or actions, is entitled to the same things, obliterates the natural justice of recognising degrees of moral standing and innate differences of true worth. A brutal killer is not the same as an innocent child. The same treatment offered to the innocent and guilty alike, becomes an injustice to the innocent. And it is never the case that universal human rights confine themselves to their original idealistic purpose. They never limit themselves to natural justice, since they are considered superior to natural justice.
Therefore something benign in seeming, like an assertion of basic human dignity, becomes malign in consequence, like a system which in the name of universal rights refuses to deport brutal savages of foreign extraction, or which lets terrorists play a legal game of demands and blackmail from their prison cells, or avoiding a cell altogether. The abstract principle of a universal right sees murderers demanding sex change operations at public expense, or foreign murderers being allowed to remain in a country because they supposedly have a universal right to a family life. These are in every case of injustice and absurdity things which obviously revolt the true order of natural justice, and things which render the system that allows them unjust to the decent majority of people.
Similarly the universal right to free speech, if applied in all ways to all men, sees a State striving to protect its own enemies and the enemies of the majority of its people, asserting that those who publicly and loudly support terrorist groups killing us have the same rights to say such things as we have to speak in our defence. Natural justice though tells me that when the State denies the freedom of its own people to speak in criticism of their government or in criticism of foreign enemies, that is an injustice and absurdity which only tyrants impose, whereas when the State prevents those aligned with foreign ideologies and terrorist groups from voicing their desire to see us killed, that is a sensible, just and sane protection to which we are rightfully entitled. Both what is said and who is speaking it matters, and this contextual reality is never acknowledged by providing the same abstract right to say anything…..regardless of who receives it.
I do not believe in advocating for the rights of Hamas terrorists, or for the rights of a depraved, terror led and terror driven culture like that of the Palestinians. I do not believe that traitors and child abusers and murders have the same rights as innocents. I do not think that backwards barbaric cultures have the same rights as advanced and decent ones. I do not see why I should offer rights to those who offer me death. I’m tired of our culture pretending that alien foreign filth who desire to see innocent deaths among my people possess some set of universal considerations they themselves do not offer to anyone.
I suppose the argument can be made that if we wish to be considered better than these people, then we must behave differently to them. We must be nobler and kinder. But the thing is I think in most instances, and this applies to the barbarians and savages we have raised amongst us regardless of their origins, the distinctions between the innocent and the guilty, between those we must protect and those we must detest, are actually very clear. I would rather that attention was focused on remembering who and what is worth protecting, rather than extending protection and consideration to our internal and external enemies.
After vile filth use public platforms to call for our murder or the murder of genuine innocents, I’m genuinely uninterested in the centrist and classical liberal approach of saying that we must honour the rights of traitors, invaders, leftists and Islamists because it is the perverse extension of protection to our vilest enemies that makes us better than them. Whether you are talking about a Third World savage storming a beach, an Islamic rapist targeting our children, a leftist progressive supporting terrorist organisations or an unintegrated immigrant ranting with spittle flecked hate against Jews, white people and western civilisation as a whole, I really, really no longer give a fuck about their free speech. I don’t.
The right is conditional, and they have broken the conditions.
Or the right is specific, and they were never endowed with it in the first place.
I believe for example in specific forms of liberty. I believe that Americans have a Constitution that is specific to America and the American people. Whilst couched in Enlightenment language and universal declarations of rights it is in fact only just when it applies to a specific people, when it applies to Americans. It’s their creation and their protection. I do not believe the framers of the Constitution really did consider the rights of a non citizen to be the same as the rights of a citizen. I do not believe they intended the Constitution as a shield for the protection of those who move to America but detest it and destroy it. Not only did they think that everything they were creating was for a specific people, some of them even outright declared that it was for a specific version of those people-for them as a moral, Christian people, and sure to be lost if they became something else.
Similarly I believe in the rights of a freeborn Englishman, as traditionally defined, and as inalienable to me and mine as the rights enshrined in the Constitution are to Americans. But in both cases the principles of our rights are not really universal at all, but inherently specific to our own people, our own kind. The act of writing these down or enshrining them in law is not the thing that makes them sacred. It is natural justice which makes them sacred. They are, then, sacred in their specificity, and without that specificity….no longer sacred, rather like the Covenant between God and Israel. As soon as it includes everyone, regardless of status, behavior or context, it becomes meaningless. The rights of the freeborn English, for me, are naturally superior to those of a Communist traitor or a foreign immigrant, and can and should be so, and always were before the absurdity of abstract universals intruded.
It is the job of my government, my State, my nation, my leaders, to defend and protect and enshrine my liberty. Nobody else’s but mine and my people. That’s the sole reason for the existence of my nation state, for the legitimacy of laws and powers it possesses, the sole determinant of whether I am obliged to defer to its authorities and submit to its rules, by choice, since I can see that they are working for me and mine. My Nation State has no higher purpose or duty than that. It has no rights outside of those which are my rights, extensions of my interest. It has no duty of care for foreign citizens, asylum seekers, immigrants and strangers. It has no right to pretend an equivalence or match between the things that are due to me, the citizen, and the things due to others. If some other group arrives and is placed before me, in law and treatment, then that insults natural justice and the purpose of nationhood.
Ultimately the rights of foreigners are in the consideration and care of their own nations, and nothing to do with the purpose of my nation. This is not by the way the same thing as extreme isolationism. There may be such a thing as a genuine alliance with other nations and other people, which like friendship between individuals can impose duties actions on us. But these other nations must be real and genuine friends, which are exceedingly rare, and helping them must never take precedence over our own protection. Again, natural justice tells us when their actions are just, too, and how absurd it is to suffer or spend on behalf of an enemy out of some universal claim which can cite no real examples of friendship in both directions.
Aiding an ally when it benefits us too makes perfect sense. A universal principle of foreign aid does not. Welcoming an immigrant who genuinely wishes to adopt our ways and be loyal to us makes sense, where adopting savages who will not integrate does not. These are very simple and obvious distinctions which natural justice, doing that which morally fits human nature and experience in a natural way, recognises and honours. Such distinction are obliterated by universal human rights, which show no modification by the differences applying to particular cases.
The following things are true:
A universal abstract rule is the delight of the theoretician and the bane of true and natural justice. What the theorist delights in will nine times out of ten make the majority of people suffer. The best ideas become restraining morals we impose on ourselves. The worst ideas become oppressive perversions we impose on others. Most theorists are better at construction the latter rather than the former. So the first problem is the inability of an abstract universal to deal with reality, which is always paricular and contextual.
The universal human right inevitably includes human beings who don’t deserve it, and can be an automatic injustice when it protects and defends those who neither warrant nor deserve the kind of defence and protection one should apply to the worthy and the innocent.
Over time the malign and the corrupt will exploit a universal abstract right to play the system and get what they want, and in every instance this will gradually result in the universal human right to do harm in one form or another or the exploitation of these rights for the purposes of evil.
Many of the worst injustices of modern times in the western world derive from the distortion of a claimed universal human right, and the abandonment of any older sense of natural justice and an older and more just discrimination of rights based on traditional and reliable moral codes.
We need to abandon the concept of universal human rights before we can again assert the rights which are most natural and just. Natural justice is superior to its replacement and developments in the last 60-80 years have proven this to be true.
Superb essay!
"The right is conditional, and they have broken the conditions." Exactly so! With rights come responsibilities - this is what we, as English people, have learnt from the cradle. It is the unspoken agreement between us all and it has been trashed by socialism.
You tackled beautifully an universal issue that shouldn’t be avoided.
In US, we have many times written laws but sometimes it takes guts to apply them. In today’s essay, Jeff Childers: “… In a case that could redefine the reach of presidential war powers, the Fifth Circuit is the first to weigh whether the President can invoke the Alien Enemies Act of 1798 (AEA) —a dusty relic of the John Adams era— to summarily deport alleged members of a Venezuelan street gang. The law, originally designed to empower the president to detain or expel nationals of hostile nations during wartime or invasion, has been used only sparingly in U.S. history— mostly during declared wars.
But Trump’s Justice Department argued that the gang Tren de Aragua, which it claims has infiltrated 40 states and is tied to Venezuela’s Maduro regime, constitutes a modern-day invasion.”